TABLE OF CONTENTS
GENERAL INTRODUCTION
Kant’s ethical thought is possibly both the finest
and most characteristic product of the Enlightenment period. His ethical
thought is a best resource in normative theories, in ethics, political
philosophy and public policy. His ethical theory is not simply a morality of
serious principles but an ethics of mutual respect and self-esteem. It is
grounded on the dignity of the rational nature, and includes the respect for
individual rights and the equal value of human beings.
Kant’s philosophy in
its original form had contributed a lot to the social, political and economical
spheres of then Europe. It also promoted feeling of tolerance towards religions
and different cultures. He tried to show that the laws of nature and laws of
morality are grounded in human reason itself. He has certainly done a
commendable effort in distinguishing difference between nature and freedom.
Ultimately, Kant held the view that both the laws of nature and the laws of
free human conduct must be compatible, because they are both product of human
thought imposed by us on the data of our experience by the exercise of our own
power to reason. He distinguished philosophy as science of human being.
This is clearly stated in his last book, The Conflict of the Faculties (1798)
as “Philosophy is not some sort of representations, concepts and ideas, or
science of all sciences, or anything of this sort; rather it is a science of
human beings.”
Kant
derived the fundamental principles of human thought and action, from human
sensibility, understanding and reason and all of them derived as a source of
human’s autonomy. He balanced these principles against the external sensations
and the internal inclinations beyond our own control. He tried to integrate
these principles into human autonomy as both its foundation and ultimate value
and goal. In his works, Critique of Practical Reason and Groundworks
of Metaphysics of Morals, he argued that, “Reason as the source of the
ideal of systematicity is the source of the fundamental law of morality and the
consciousness of our own freedom, which is the source of all value and that we
can postulate the fundamental dogmas of Christianity, our own immortality and
the existence of God as practical presupposition of our moral conduct.”
Ethics
deals with the human nature. When I thought of doing my dissertation on the
nature of human being, I thought it is explicitly right to analyze human being
from an ethical perspective. While analyzing the ethical concepts of various
philosophers I found the ethical principles of Immanuel Kant quiet interesting,
especially his Categorical Imperatives and Postulates of morality.
In the contemporary consumerist society, where everything including human being
is considered just as a commodity, and in a use and through
culture, I found his proclamation to consider humans as an end in themselves is meaningful.
My
dissertation with the title, Human as an
Ethical Being: A Descriptive Study on Kantian Anthropology, is an effort to
find out the essence of Kantian morality in defining human as an ethical
person. For that purpose I tried to analyze the Kantian concept of Autonomy,
Free will, freedom, obligation etc. because they are important elements of
human moral nature. They are capable of raising questions like whether man is
free or not, is it justifiable to harm others in order to save one’s own life
etc.
The
first chapter deals with the life and works of Immanuel Kant, where it is
divided into two parts, in the first part his childhood, his life as a student
and a professor; background of his philosophical thinking etc. is discussed.
The second part summarized explanation of his three important critiques, the Critique of Pure Reason, the Critique
of Practical Reason and the Critique
of Judgment.
The
second chapter is the core of this dissertation. It is the discussion on the
anthropological concepts of Kant assuming human as a moral being. This
chapter consists of five parts. The first
part is a discussion on the autonomy and concept of free will in human
beings. The second part is a brief discussion on his postulates of morality such as God, immortality and freedom. The
third part mainly discusses on the concept of freedom in human beings.
The fourth part is on his conception of obligation. In the fifth and last part
there is a broad discussion on his Categorical Imperatives where Kant
establishes certain underlining principles on morality.
The
third chapter deals mainly with the criticism of Kant’s moral principles. It
was an elaborate task for me to critically evaluate his philosophy, I tried
mainly to analyze whether his ethical thoughts are still applicable in the
present day society. This
chapter consists of three parts; the first part deals with the criticism of
Kant’s ethics in general in relation to the contemporary society, in the second
part I tried to analyze his postulates of morality and the third part is the
analysis of his Categorical Imperatives.
CHAPTER
1
LIFE
AND WORKS OF IMMANUEL KANT
INTRODUCTION
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) was an influential
philosopher of the European Enlightenment. He eradicated the last traces of
medieval worldview from modern philosophy, joined the key ideas of earlier
rationalism and empiricism into a powerful model of the subjective origins of
the fundamental principles of both science and morality, and laid the ground
for much in the philosophy of 19th and 20th centuries. Above all, Kant was the philosopher of human autonomy, the view that by the use
of our own reason in its broadest sense human beings can discover and live up
to the basic principles of knowledge and action without outside assistance,
above all without divine support or divine intervention.
Kant laid foundations of his theory of
knowledge in his monumental Critique of Pure Reason (1781). He described
the fundamental principle of morality in The Groundwork for the Metaphysics
of morals (1785) and the Critique of Practical Reason (1788). His
influence on the development of science, theology, and philosophy is very
valuable. He offered solutions to problems that have always had the utmost
relevance for the thinker: such as, what are morality and duty? What are truth,
beauty, and justice? What can and cannot be science? In doing so, he liberated
science from religion and religion from known. He clarified the difference
between knowledge and faith and established a branch of philosophy where he
gave importance to empiricist and rationalist way of thinking.
This chapter consists of two parts. At first there
is a short description about the life of Kant and in the second part the
important works of Kant is discussed. In the first part his childhood, life as
student and a professor; consequences which led to his critical thinking, the
background of his thought etc. are discussed. In the second part there is a
study of his tree Critiques – The Critique of Pure Reason, where he
deals with the critical examination of reason in relation to sense experience;
The Critique of Practical Reason, where the practical philosophy of Kant
is presented and The Critique of Judgment, where the concepts like the
beauty, sublime and good are discussed.
1.1
A
BRIEF BIOGRAPHY
Immanuel
Kant was born on 22 April 1724 in Konigsberg, the capital of East Prussia
(today Kaliningrad, U.S.S.R.) as the fourth of nine children, of whom five--two
younger sisters, an older sister, and a brother. His father, Johann Georg, was a harness
maker. His mother, the former Anna Regina Reuter, was the daughter of a
saddler, was born in Nuremberg. His parents were poor but devout followers of
pietism, a Lutheran revival movement stressing love and good works, simplicity
of worship, and individual access to God. He was educated at the local high
school, the Collegium Fridericianum, there Kant spent eight years – six days a
week, from seven in the morning until four in the afternoon-, studying Latin,
Greek, Hebrew, French, Mathematics and Theology. In1740 at the age of sixteen
Kant entered the University of Konigsberg, where he studied mathematics,
physics, philosophy, theology and classical Latin literature. His leading
teacher was Martin Knutenz (1713-51), who introduced him, to both Wolffian
Philosophy and Newtonian physics, and who inspired some of Kant’s own later
views and philosophical independence by his advocacy of physical influx against
the pre-established harmony of Leibniz and Wolff.[5]
Kant spent seven years in the University, but was not able to take a graduate.
Due to financial hardship he had to leave the University, the death of his
mother in1737 and death of his father in1746 also paved way for this. After
leaving the University, in order to meet his financial needs Kant was employed
for a few years as a tutor in a number of families in different parts of East
Prussia.
In 1749 Kant published his first work Thoughts on the True Estimation of Living Forces, it was an unsuccessful attempt to
mediate between Cartesian and Leibnizian theories of physical forces. Kant then
worked as a tutor, serving in households near Konigsberg for the next eight
years. With the financial support of a friend, he returned to the University in
1755 and took a doctorate. In the same year he was given permission to teach at
Konigsberg as a Privetodzent or
Lecturer, a lowly position with prestige and no salary except for student fees. Circumstances forced him to live in a one- room apartment furnished only with a
bed, a table and a chair. In order to supplement his meager income he worked as
assistant librarian in the Royal Castle. In 1756 he tried to obtain Knutenz’s
chair rendered vacant by the latter’s death. But Knutenz had been an extra
ordinary professor and the government influenced by financial considerations,
left the post unfulfilled.
In 1746 Kant was offered the chair of
poetry, but he declined it wisely, to afford the post of professor. In 1769 he
refused a similar offer from Jena. Finally in March 1770 at the age of
forty-six he was appointed ordinary professor of logic and metaphysics
at Konigsberg. His period as a Lecture lasted therefore from 1755 until 1770.
He taught a wide variety of subjects, including Physics, Mathematics and
Physical Geography as well as Philosophy. His lectures were salted with humor and even with stories. In his courses, his
main aim was to stimulate his hearers to think for themselves, to stand on
their own feet. Over the preceding years Kant has published a number of works,
the majority on scientific cum-metaphysical subjects, which has earned him a
secure reputation with Germany as a powerful, independent thinker. During these
years he received offers from other universities but he refused in order to
remain in his home city. He was such a person that any change in his physical
environment, including the furniture, made him uneasy. The following Anecdote
is important. In the 1780s he developed the habit of gazing out the window at a
distant church steeple as he worked or meditated. After a few years trees
growing in a neighbor’s garden obscured the steeple. He became restless and was
unable to work. The problem was resolved when the neighbor, who admired the
famous man, readily agreed to trim the offending trees. Kant refused to travel.
He never saw a mountain or the sea, Although Baltic was only an hour away.
One can neither traces
back the exact date of the starting of Kantian thinking or his rejection of
Leibniz-Wolffian system of philosophy and beginning of working out his own
system. He continued giving courses of lectures on subjects like anthropology
and geography on the conviction that students need factual knowledge of this
kind, in order that they might understand the part played by experience in our
knowledge. The most influential areas of Kant’s thoughts were religious,
political and scientific. It was because of the background of the Pietist
tradition. Politically, Kant was a man of Enlightenment who spoke up for human
rights, professed the equality of mankind, and advocated representative
government. He was greatly influenced by French thinker Rousseau, who has
raised questions on the social nature of morality and the problem of individual
feeling. In science he studied the works of Sir Isaac Newton, which served as
the basis for his lectures in physics and natural philosophy.
He published a number of books in his
life time they are as follows: The Critique of Pure Reason was published
in 1781. In 1783 he published Prolegomena
to any Future Metaphysics, in 1785 the Fundamental
Principles of Metaphysics of Morals,
In 1786 the Metaphysical first principle
of Natural Science, In 1787 The Second Edition of Metaphysics of Pure Reason, In 1788 the Critique of Practical Reason, In 1790 the Critique of Practical Judgment, In 1793 Religion within the bounds of Reason Alone, in 1795 a little
treatise On Perpetual Peace, and in
1787 The Metaphysics of Morals.
Only
once did Kant come into collision with political authority. This was connected
with his Religion within the Bounds of
Reason Alone. In 1792 the second part of this work, titled On the
Conflict of Good Principle Within the Evil, failed to pass the censorship,
on the account that it attacked Biblical authority. However the whole works
consisting of four parts, was approved by the faculty of Theology in Konigsberg
and the Philosophical faculty of Jena and was published in 1793. In 1794
Frederick William II, expressed the displeasure at the book and accused Kant
for misrepresenting and depreciating many fundamental principles of the scriptures
and of Christianity. He promised the king to refrain from making public
pronouncements, whether in writings or in lecturing on religion. However on the
king’s death he was released from his promise and in 1798 he published The Conflict of the Faculties, where he
discussed the relation between Theology in the sense of Biblical belief, and
Philosophy or the critical reason.
The salient feature of Kant’s character
was mainly his moral earnestness and his devotion to the idea of duty. He was a
sociable man, who was so kind and benevolent. He was systematically careful in
money matters and assisted a number of poor persons. He was not an orthodox
Christian but he had a real belief in God. Kant died on February 12th,
1804.
1.2 IMPORTANT WORKS
Kant’s philosophical writings can be classified into
two periods, which before 1770, usually referred to as pre-critical, and
after 1770, usually referred to as critical. The word critical comes
from Kant’s own description of his philosophical forms of critical idealism,
an idealism built on the basis of powers of reason alone. The summary of Kant’s three important critiques is being discussed here.
1.2.1 The Critique of
Pure Reason
The Critique of Pure Reason by Immanuel Kant,
(first published in 1781 and the second edition 1787) is one of the most
influential works in the history of philosophy, also referred to as Kant's
first critique. In the preface to the first edition Kant explains what he means
by a critique of pure reason: "I mean by this a critique of, the faculty
of reason in general, in respect of all knowledge after which it may strive
independently of all experience." An explanation given to Kant’s Critique is
that “Critique means a critical examination in two senses: a positive
evaluation of reason as applied to sense experience, leading to a defense of
mathematics and science against such skeptical attacks as Hume’s; and a
negative evaluation of reason when it speculates beyond the limits of
experience.” In thus second sense the Critique has strong doubts on the validity of
classical metaphysics, and this was probably its most important contribution. Kant
began the work with the promise to submit reason to a critique, in order to
obtain a decision about the possibility or impossibility of metaphysics in
general and the determination in its sources, its scope and its boundaries. The
chief question would be “what and how much can understanding and reason know
apart from all experience?”
The most important points in the Critique of Pure Reason are following:
The
three main divisions are the Transcendental Aesthetic, Transcendental
Analytic, and Transcendental Dialectic. Aesthetic is concerned with the power of sensibility, and with
mathematics inclusive of geometry. In Transcendental Aesthetic Kant claims that
“mathematics necessarily deals with space and time and claims that these are a
priori forms of human sensibility that condition what is apprehended through
the senses.” It also covers some of the fundamental
pre-scientific propositions about space and time, e.g. regarding their number
of dimension. The Analytic is
concerned with the power of understanding, and with metaphysics of experience
and natural science. In Transcendental Analytic he maintains that
physics is a priori and synthetic because in its ordering of experience it uses
concepts of a special sort. These concepts –categories, are a priori and
opposed to empirical. The Dialectic is concerned with the
power of reason and with transcendent metaphysics which divides into three bodies
of doctrine: the metaphysics of soul (rational psychology), of the world as a
whole (rational cosmology) and of God (rational theology).
Together the Aesthetic, Analytic and Dialectic fall under the heading Transcendental
Doctrine of Elements because each deals with a different element of
cognition; the Aesthetic with
intuitions, the Analytic with
concepts and the Dialectic with
ideas. What we ordinarily refer to as intellect is split by Kant into two
separate powers, understanding and reason.
The
Transcendental Doctrine of Method gives the epistemological and
metaphysical argument of the Critique with
reflection on its methodology. It also contains a section called The Canon
of Pure Reason, which contains important pointers to the rest of Kant’s
Critical system. The clarity of the Critique
can be seen more clearly in the conclusion of the work. The real division is
between, on the one hand, the Aesthetic and Analytic, which are
jointly concerned with knowable objects, on the other hand Dialectic is
concerned with objects that cannot be known. The Aesthetic and Analytic
are positive that; they prove that we can have knowledge of things which we can
experience. The Aesthetic deals with sensible that is the
spatio-temporal aspect of knowable objects, aesthetic argues that space
and time are the necessary forms within which the mind the mind has sense
experience. And therefore, mathematics concerned with the structure of space
and time is a valid science. Analytic deals with the sensible and
conceptual aspects, including the concepts of substance and causality. Jointly
they express the metaphysics of experience. The Dialectic is
negative; it seeks to prove that we cannot have knowledge of anything outside
experience. It denies legitimacy to the other kind of metaphysics –
transcendental metaphysics. When he reworked the Critique of Pure Reason in 1787, he added two more
topics, they are – The Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics
and The Metaphysical Elements of Natural
Science.
1.2.2 The Critique of Practical
Reason
The
Critique of Practical Reason is the second of Immanuel Kant's three
critiques, first published in 1788. It follows on from Kant's Critique of Pure
Reason and deals with his moral philosophy. The second Critique exercised a
decisive influence over the subsequent development of the field of ethics and
moral philosophy, beginning with Fichte's doctrine of Science and Becoming
during the 20th century, the principal reference point for deontological moral
philosophy. The first Critique was a critique of the pretensions of pure theoretical reason
to attain metaphysical truths beyond the light of applied theoretical reason.
The conclusion was that pure theoretical reason must be restrained, because it
produces confused arguments when applied outside of its appropriate sphere.
However, the Critique of Practical Reason is not a critique of pure practical
reason, but rather a defense of it as being capable of grounding behavior
superior to that grounded by desire-based practical reasoning. The second
critique is far shorter and much less complicated. Here the human moral
situation is clarified by reference to a notion of “holly will.”
Critique of Practical Reason
contains definitive statements of his ethical theories. Kant’s major ethical
doctrines are derived from the conception of Practical Reason itself- i.e. of
rationality as capable of being a ground of action. He further explains man
alone posses this capacity, the lower animal act from natural impulsions. Man
also, since he is an animal, is moved by impulses and inclinations and
naturally seeks the satisfaction of his own desires, but being rational, he
finds himself subjected to a moral ought, to the command, so act that you
can will, the maxim of your conduct to be a universal law. Kant calls this
basic moral principle as Categorical Imperative. Since it is for each
man, a dictate of his own rational nature and not imposed upon him, it
represents the self-legislation or autonomy of the will. In contrast action
which is not motivated merely by natural inclination represents a harmony of
the will, a subordinate of the will to impulses and desires.
There is only one strict motive, the motive to act
from respect for the moral law itself. Man inherits dignity and value and
nothing can be substituted over it. This principle of value of human being is
expressed in the second categorical imperative. “So act so always to treat the
humanity, whether in your own person or in that of any other, always as an end
withal, never as a means only.” Moral value or virtue is thus the supreme good. The only qualified good in the
world is the good will. All men by nature deserve happiness and those
who are virtues deserve it. The highest and complete good is the virtue. On the
basis of these ethical doctrines, in the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant
reinstates as belief what he refuses to recognize as demonstrable knowledge. We
can’t avoid the moral command; hence we must accept what is essential to its
validity. Such implications are freedom of will, immortality and existence of
God. Man as an observable actuality is a natural phenomenon is explainable as
the effect of natural cause. The validity of moral imperatives requires us to
believe that man is also a transcendental being and free initiator of this
moral conduct. Moral law commands a perfection of our will and purity of our
motives, which are not naturally attainable. Since validity of this command
requires possibility of its fulfillment, we must believe in a destiny beyond
this natural life. We must be bound to act without regard to our own happiness,
though happiness is the sum total of all that we desire, would not be a
rational and valid command unless in the ultimate nature of things. There is
some reconciliation between virtuous action and happiness thus which is thus
deserved. Hence believe in God as a power which makes for righteousness is
rationally impelled. Thus God, reason and immortality are valid as postulates
of Practical Reason.
1.2.3
The Critique of Judgment
The
Critique of Judgment is the third critique of Immanuel Kant,
which published in 1790. It lays the foundations for modern aesthetics. It has
two parts. The first part; The Critique of Aesthetic Judgment discusses
the four possible reflective judgments; the agreeable, the beautiful,
the sublime, and the good. In reflective judgment we seek to find unknown
universals for given particulars. The second part The Critique of Teleological Judgment discusses way of judging things according to
their ends (telos: Greek for end) is logically connected to the first
discussion at least regarding beauty but suggests a kind of (self-)
purposiveness (that is, meaningfulness known by one's self). The general topic of both parts is our imitation of purposivenes in things
which cannot be scientifically and demonstrably ascribed to any purpose.
Idealist philosophers consider this Critique as the capstone of his ethical
philosophy. Empiricists regard it as an afterthought, which threatens the
integrity of his system.
In the second part, on the
discussion of the aesthetics, about the experience of the beauty he says, is a
“disinterested and impersonal pleasure felt in the apprehension of the form of
an object.” The aesthetic satisfaction arises when what is presented is not taken as the
object of any specific purpose or desire or any specific theoretical concept,
but so excites the play of the faculty as bring the imagination into the
harmony with understanding. The felt harmony is formal purposiveness of
it. When such contemplative pleasure is judged to be found up with the object,
not only for the subject in question but for everyone the object is called
beautiful. The explanation lies on the fact that, when a person contemplates on
an object and finds it beautiful there is a certain harmony between his
imagination and his understanding of which he is aware of what is happening in
the object. The feeling of the sublime is due to the felt disparity between imagination and
conception. When we dispassionately contemplate a thing which either in the
magnitude or in its power is such that no image we can frame in adequate to the
idea of it, we recognize the object as the sublime.
CONCLUSION
Immanuel
Kant, one of the key figures in modern philosophy, is important not only for
his critical approach in philosophy, but also for his method of synthesizing
empiricist and rationalist way of thinking. It was he who introduced the new method
of Copernican Revolution in the vast ocean of philosophy. The family
background, education, areas of socialization and culture of society where one
lives, are the elements which highly influence the character of an individual.
While analyzing various philosophers, we come to know that behind the
development of every philosopher, there was a vast horizon of experiences,
concepts and thoughts upon which one could philosophize.
As an introductory chapter of my
dissertation in this chapter I made an attempt to look into the life of
Immanuel Kant. Kant had a background of strong family life in his childhood,
but in his teenage he lost his parents and suffered a lot to continue his
education. The hard experiences which he confronted in his early life might
have touched him a lot. Beyond that his incomparable intelligence also has an
important role behind the development of his thought. Thus the first part of
this chapter was an attempt to understand the background of his philosophizing
and to know the fact how the life situations of Kant helped him in developing
his thinking structure.
In the second part of this chapter an
attempt was made to look briefly into his important works such as The
Critique of Pure reason, The Critique of Practical Reason and The
Critique of Judgment respectively. I tried to study on his three main
critiques because; these three critiques include the sum and substance of his
philosophy. It helped me to understand the basic concepts and the Kantian style
of philosophizing. The Critique of Pure Reason was a critical examination in two senses: a positive
evaluation of reason as applied to sense experience, leading to a defense of
mathematics and science against such skeptical attacks as Hume’s; and a
negative evaluation of reason when it speculates beyond the limits of experience.
The Critique of Practical Reason deals with his practical philosophy. It is
far shorter and much less complicated. It is not a critique of the first
critique, but rather a defense of it, as being capable of grounding behavior
superior to that grounded by desire-based practical reasoning. Here the human
moral situation is clarified by reference to a notion of holly will. The
Critique of Judgment mainly deals with the concepts like, good, sublime
etc. and lays foundation for modern aesthetics.
CHAPTER 2
KANTIAN ANTHROPOLOGY: HUMAN AS AN ETHICAL BEING
INTRODUCTION
Traditionally
we consider human being as a rational animal. As we relate him with the
society, we have to consider him not simply as a rational being but as a
rational ethical being, because humans are beings of actions. They are the one
who posses certain values in their life. Ethics is the reflective study of
certain values that concern human beings. A sense of ethical values informs
people’s lives, directly in deciding what to do, and in their comments and
judgments on people and actions, including their own. People try, in many ways,
to shape their lives by reference to such values: they think, even if not very
explicitly, that some kind of life are more worth living than others, and try
to bring up their children to share their outlook, or perhaps to develop
another which equally they hope to be able to respect. Ethics tries to
understand certain kinds of reasons for these actions of human beings.
Ethics deals with values, with good
and bad, with right and wrong. What we do and what we don’t do is a subject of
ethical thinking. Anyone who thinks about what he or she ought to do is,
consciously or unconsciously, involved in ethics. One of the striking features
of Kant’s anthropology is that, his morals or practical philosophy is developed
not merely as a theoretical philosophy, but as a practical implication. Kantian
philosophy, in a greater sense has proclaimed the dignity of human beings;
mainly through the concept of freedom, autonomy, obligation and free will. This
chapter is an attempt to look into the ethical concepts of Kant, in order to
analyze how the concept of human being is developed in Kantian thinking and
also to discover how he proved human as an ethical being through his moral
principles.
This chapter consists of five parts.
The first part discusses the autonomy and concept of free will in
human beings. The second part is a brief discussion on his postulates of
morality such as God, immortality and freedom, where he discusses the basic
character of humans, as ethical beings. The third part mainly discusses on the
concept of freedom in human beings. The fourth part is on his conception
of obligation. The fifth and last part of this chapter discusses his Categorical
Imperatives where Kant establishes certain underlining principles on
morality.
2.1
HUMAN
AS
AN
AUTONOMOUS
BEING
While
analyzing the historical reference of the concept – autonomy, we get the
source from an early work Discourses (1531) by Machiavelli who combined
the two senses of autonomy as the freedom from dependence and the
power of self-legislate. Martin Luther in his work Freedom of A
Christian (1520) has also mentioned about the political aspects of autonomy,
which developed in the early modern city-state. He translated the concept of
autonomy as freedom from dependence into the spiritual, new and inner, man’s
freedom from the body and its inclinations as well as to obey the freedom of
God’s Law. Kant’s account of autonomy in his practical philosophy in its turn
marks a philosophical transposition and critique of Luther’s religious autonomy
into moral autonomy.
At
the heart of Kant's moral theory is the position that rational human wills are
autonomous. Kant saw autonomy as important in understanding and justifying the
authority moral requirements have over us. Kant’s practical philosophy combines
the two aspects of autonomy within an account of the determination of the will.
His position emerged from the critique of a number of then prevailing
perspectives. As with Rousseau, whose views influenced Kant, freedom does not
consist in being bound by no law, but by laws that are in some sense of one's
own making. These thinking included his pre-critical opposition to the accounts
of moral actions proposed by the dominant rational, perfectionist accounts
moral actions proposed by the dominant rational, perfectionist account of the
Wolffian school and the contemporary British theory of moral sense, pietist
movements etc. he later identified that all these accounts are based on hetronomous
principles and sought to develop a moral philosophy based on autonomous
principle of self-legislation. The idea of freedom as autonomy thus goes beyond the merely negative
sense of being free from influences on our conduct originating
outside of ourselves. It contains first and foremost the idea of laws made and
laid down by one and that have decisive authority over oneself.
Kant’s
attribution of autonomy to every normal adult was a radical break with
predominant views of moral capacity of ordinary people. The natural law
theorists whose work was influential through the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries did not fully concerned that the most people could know, everything
that morally requires of them even without being told. The lawyers were
admitted that God has given human the ability to know the basic principles of
morality. But they held the view that many are not able to understand all the
moral requirements implicit in the principles. They thought of morality as
obligation imposed by law. For them, God is the legislator of moral law, and
humans, his unruly subjects. Though most of the people are unwilling to obey
the laws of nature, and must be made to do so through the treatment of
punishment for noncompliance. A number of philosophers before Kant had begun to
reject the natural lawyer’s law estimate of human moral capacity, and to
present theories in which a greater amount of self governance is attributed to
people.
Christian
Wolf whose philosophy dominated German universities when Kant was a student
argued that we can be self governed because we can see for ourselves what the
consequences of our actions will be, and can tell which action can bring about
the greatest amount of perfection. Since we are always drawn to act so as to
bring about what we believe is the greatest amount of perfection, Wolf says we
are bound to do what we think will be for the best and this seems to him to
explain the necessity we call moral. In political matters we are obliged to act
by sanctions imposed by a political ruler; but in morality we obliged ourselves
to act through our perception of perfection. Hence in morality we are self
governed. We need no sanctions to move us to act for the best.
For
Kant this theory was not acceptable. He holds the view that Wolf’s thinking
implied that the only necessity involved in morality is the necessity of using
a means to an end to desire. If you do not want the end there is no need for
you to do the acts that leads to it. Thus with the introduction of Kant’s
ethical thought he made the concept of autonomy rather distinct from the
early thinkers. He made the concept of autonomy independent from external
forces.
At
the centre of Kant’s ethical theory is the claim that normal adults are capable
of being fully self - governing in moral matters. In Kant’s terminology, we are
autonomous. Autonomy involves two components. The first is that no
authority external to ourselves is needed to constitute or inform us of the
demands of morality. We can each know without being told what we ought to do
because moral requirements are requirements we impose on ourselves. The second
is that in self-government we can effectively control ourselves. The obligation
we impose upon ourselves override all other calls for action, and frequently
run counter to our desires. We nonetheless have a sufficient motive to act as
we ought. Hence no external source of motivation is needed for our
self-legislation to be effective in controlling our behaviour.
Kant
thinks that autonomy has basic social and political implications. It can be
explained in relation to the parliamentary system of democracy; a state is free
when its citizens are bound only by laws in some sense of their own making — created
and put into effect, by vote or by elected representatives. Here the laws of
that state express the will of the citizens who are bound by them. Then the
source of legitimate political authority is not external to its citizens, but
internal to them, internal to the will of the people. An autonomous
state is thus one in which the authority of its laws is in the will of the
people in that state. In similar way, we can say a person is free when he/she bounds only by his/her
own will and not by the will of another. His/her actions then express not the
will of someone or something else. The authority of the principles binding his/her
will is then also not external to his/her will. So autonomy, when applied to an
individual, ensures that the source of the authority of the principles that
bind him/her is in his/her own will.
Kant always held the view that the moral need
for our autonomy to express itself was compatible with certain kinds of social
regulation. There is no place for others to tell us what morality requires, nor
has anyone the authority to do so – not our neighbors, not the magistrates and
their law, not even the religious persons. Because we are autonomous, each one
of us must be allowed a social space within which we may freely determine our
own actions. This
freedom cannot be limited to the members of some privileged class. The
structure of society must reflect and express the common and equal moral
capacity of its members.
One of the
important argument of Kant is his claim that a rational will can only act under
the Idea of its own freedom. This argument cannot be misunderstood. In his
most famous work the Critique
of Pure Reason, he says, to argue that we have no rational basis for believing our wills to be free. This would involve,
attributing a property to our wills that they would have to have as things
in themselves apart from the causally determined world of appearances.
According to Kant, there is no rational
basis for the belief that the natural world is (or is not) arranged according
to some purpose by a Designer, the actual practices of science often
require looking for the purpose of this or that chemical, organ, creature,
environment, and so on. Thus, one engages in these natural sciences by searching
for purposes in nature. When an evolutionary biologist, looks for the purpose
of some organ in some creature, may not all believe that the creature was designed by a Deity. Practicing
biology involves searching for the purposes of the parts of living organisms.
In the same way, although there is no rational justification for the belief
that our wills are (or are not) free, the actual practice of practical
deliberation and decision consists of a search for the right casual chain of
which to be the origin — consists, that is, seeking to be the first causes of
things, wholly and completely through the exercise of one's own will.
Kant’s interest
in sociological and political implication of autonomy is shown in many places.
In the short essay what is enlightenment? Kant argues each of us to
refuse to remain under the tutelage of others. “I do not need to rely on a book
which understands for me, a pastor who has a conscience of me.” But we must think and decide for ourselves. For this public freedom of discussion
is necessary, particularly in connection with religion. Kant again says an
enlightened ruler will allow such discussion to flourish, knowing that he has
nothing to fear from it.
A
society built around the virtues of generosity and kindness is for Kant a
society requiring not only inequality but servility as well. If nothing is
properly mine except what someone graciously gives me, I am forever dependent
on how the donor feels toward me. My independence as an autonomous being is
threatened. Only if I claim that the others have to give me what is mine by
right can this be avoided. Kant did not deny the moral importance of beneficent
action, but his theoretical emphasis on the importance of obligation or moral
necessity reflects his rejection of benevolent paternalism and a servility that
goes with it, just as the centrality of autonomy in his theory shows his aim of
limiting political control of our lives. Thus for Kant autonomy is the ground of the dignity of human nature and of
every rational nature.
2.1.1
Free Will
‘Free
Will’ is a conventional name of a topic that is best discussed without
reference to the will.Its central questions are what is it to act freely? And what is it to be
morally responsible for one’s actions? Philosophers give very different answers
to these questions. Kant in his ethical discussion discusses that (i) for a
will to be free for it not to be subject to compulsion. (ii) But causality is
affirmed of compulsion and the will is subject to it by virtue of our being a
part of our natural order. (iii) What constitutes causal compulsion on the will
is what Kant calls inclination, which has its source in our sensible
nature (what Plato calls the body – the flesh in Christian
literature). Our sensible nature is what makes us part of what Kant calls the phenomenal
world where causality reigns supreme. (iv)We can be free by virtue of that
aspect of ourselves which goes beyond or transcends that in us which partakes
of the phenomenal world. This aspect is our reason and rationality.
Kant
argues that the idea of an autonomous will emerges from a consideration of the
idea of a will that is free. Rational will is the will that operates by
responding to reasons. That is, the concept of a will is that which does not
operate through the influence of factors outside of this responsiveness to
reasons. For a will to be free it is to be physically and psychologically
unforced in its operation. So, choices made because of obsessions or thought
disorders are not free in this negative sense.But for Kant, a will that operates by being determined through the natural
laws, like biology or psychology, cannot be thought of as operating by
responding to reasons.
Natural world is subjected to laws of motion
and to causality. Yet natural objects are free. The possibility of their acting
has to do with human beings having a will. This involves primarily, the
intelligibility of attributing intentional action to human beings and
this in turn is bound up with acting for a reason. Having a will
guarantees not freedom, but the possibility of this – the possibility of
acting freely. This possibility is realized when a man’s will is his own, that
is when it is not subordinate to anything external to it.
On Kant’s view there exists certain
duality in man. They inevitably belong to nature or the phenomenal world, and
they are also rational creatures and by virtue of this process the capacity to
transcend what is natural in them. Like Plato, Kant here runs together two
claims to be distinguished. (i) The first one is that the possibility of
reaction, such as human beings are capable of, involves the capacity to act
for a reason. Human beings are different from all other creatures in
possessing this capacity. Human beings acts freely when his will is autonomous
and that means when it is determined by reason. (ii) The second claim relates
to a timeless world in identity with which alone real freedom to be
achieved.
Kant
represents the conflict as between man’s appetitive nature which has to do with
the sense of sensuality (Kant refers to it as inclination) and reason or
man’s rationality. The word inclination covers many different things as it is
normally used, that means to act in accordance with one’s impulses. As for
human beings belonging to the natural world by the virtue of their
inclinations, is simply used here to signify man’s appetitive nature. Kant
along with many other philosophers agree that a man whose actions are random is
not charge of what he does and so is not responsible for his actions. Such a
man far from being free is really subject to the moment. The will when it is free is not lawless. Regularity may be essential to human
free will; he recognizes that the kind of regularity in question is not causal
regularity. Kant points out that the sense in which considerations of reason
govern the will is different from the sense which laws of nature govern natural
phenomena: according to Kant, only a rational being has the power to act in
accordance with the idea of laws – that is in accordance with principles- and
only so has he a will.
2.2
Postulates of Morality
Kant proposes three postulates in
his ethical theory namely freedom, God and Immortality taking into account the
fact that man is not purely a rational being but a creature haunted by
inclinations. The three postulates are not theoretical dogmas but are presuppositions
having necessary practical reference. God as postulate by Kant is not the God
of religion. The postulate of God has origin in one’s own reason which would
necessarily mean that submitting to will of God is submitting to one’s own
reason. The concept of God arises because the relationship between moral law
and happiness is not guaranteed in this world. So here God comes to the rescue
and thus necessitates the compatibility of virtue and realization of highest
good. The postulate of immortality is very much interwoven with the postulate
of God. Taking into account the sensuous nature of human beings, Kant states
that it is very difficult for a man to be righteous without hope. Immortality
guarantees this hope and ensures that there is a place sufficient for the
reckoning of happiness in proportion to worthiness to be happy. The postulate
of freedom has a special position among the other two postulates. Freedom is an
a priori that we may not understand but we know it as the condition of the
moral law which we may know. It is because of freedom that God and Immortality
gain objective reality and legitimacy and subjective necessity. Then freedom
can be considered as the keystone of the structure of pure reason.
According to Kant, a postulate is “a
theoretical propositions which is not as such demonstrable but which is an
inseparable corollary of an a priori unconditionally valid practical law.” So
the postulate becomes part of the Kant’s ethical structure but he makes it
clear that the postulates have no theoretical role. Though we have no
intuitions to apply the concepts of freedom, God and immortality; no
theoretical knowledge is possible. As Kant makes it clear, “A postulate of
practical reason is an object of rational belief, but the reasons for the
belief are practical and moral. The person needs the belief as a condition for
obedience to the moral law and it is this combined with the categorical nature
of that law which justifies the belief. Although the beliefs are theoretical in
form- will is free, there is God-their basis and their functions are practical.
The postulates are indemonstrable
and are necessary for practical function. A postulate in general sense means to
suggest or accept that something is true so that it can be used the basis of a
theory. A postulate of pure practical reason is a factual proposition which combines
the two following characteristics: (i) there is no convincing factual evidence
for or against it. (ii) Unless a person accepts it, he finds himself in the
practical dilemma of knowing himself to be under an unconditional obligation to
strive to bring about a certain state of affairs is in principle unrealizable.So
the postulates are not theoretical dogmas but presuppositions having a
necessary practical reference, which do not extend speculative cognition but
give objective reality to the idea of speculative reason in general.
The
postulates do not give us knowledge of their objects instead they enable us to
assert their reality. “when these ideas of God, of an intelligible world and of
immortality are predicates which are taken from our own nature, we must regard
this determination neither as a sensualising of these pure ideas nor as a
transcendent knowledge of supersensible objects; for the predicates we use are
only understanding and will, and, indeed, these regarded only in that relation
to each other in which we are required by the moral law to regard them.” It is only from the practical point of view that we have the postulates and it
will be foolish to go behind the practical postulates in search of theoretical
proof. Now let us discuss the three postulates of morality by Immanuel
Kant.
2.2.1 The Postulate of God
While discussing about the postulate
of God, Kant says that, the postulate of God is based on the moral proof rather
than the theoretical proof. Kant criticizes the attempts to employ reason to
theology and giving out theoretical proofs and dogmas of things in phenomenal
world which the reason of human beings is unable to reach. In the Critique of Pure Reason Kant writes,
“All attempts to employ reason in theology in any way merely speculative manner
are altogether fruitless and by their very nature null and void…the only
theology of reason which is possible is that which is based upon moral laws” Kant again asserts that the idea of God should originate in our own reason and
as mentioned earlier the God postulated by Kant is not the God of religion but
that which origin in one’s own reason.
Why do the postulates of God come
into picture? Kant says, “This system of self-rewarding morality is only an
idea, the realization of which rests on the condition that everyone does what
he should. But his is no reason for anyone for not being moral. Kant would say that when
we have a good reason to believe, that we can get to the goal which we follow.
But in the natural world the goal imposed by morality is not always
realized. The relationship between happiness and moral law is not guaranteed
although. Kant again says, “To be happy is necessarily the desire of every
rational finite being, and thus it is an unavoidable finite being, and thus it
is an unavoidable determinant of its faculty of desire.” If
this was guaranteed then we would not have seen people who lack good will
enjoying un-interrupted prosperity and morally good people should experience
general happiness to the exact proportion to their moral goodness. So we must
therefore postulate as it were unnatural world, beyond the temporal frame of
ordinary existence and ruled by a wise benevolent and powerful God, in which
the ideal results of morality will become actual. In particular, God turns out
to be the highest original good. From whom the highest derived good,
the happiness of all as a result of morality of all is derived.
The assumption of the existence of
God can never be made the basis of our obligation to obey the moral law. It is
in fact a moral necessity to assume the existence of God. The postulate of God
is a need or requirement of our moral consciousness or a moral necessity which
is subjective and not objective which means that it is not itself a duty. It is
in no way connected to the consciousness of our duty. The divine will is the
motive to action, not ground of it.
Kant stresses that the properties of
Omnipotence, Omniscience and Omnipresence can be assigned to God to play his
moral role of guaranteeing the possibility of the highest good and that have no
basis for assigning any other properties to God. God is not a metaphysical
concept, original being, first cause not blindly working eternal root of all
things. It functions in the thinking of a moral agent and exercise a real
influence on human actions.
2.2.2
The postulate of Immortality
The
postulate of God has a close affinity to the postulate of Immortality in the
realization of the moral Ideal. As Kant states in his critique, “the belief in
God and another world is so interwoven with my moral sentiment.” The
postulate of immortality was taken seriously by Kant even when he was
traditionalistic in his rationalism. The premise of immortality was found in
the incomplete harmony between morality and its consequences in the world. He
was of the view that the belief in immortality has to be based on the moral
disposition and not one hope of future rewards.
In Critique of Practical Reason, Kant says that the
belief in immortality is based on a notable characteristic of our nature, never
to be capable of being satisfied by what is temporal. Basing
himself on the principle of purposiveness, Kant bases his first argument for
immortality. As nothing is purposeless each organ or faculty into the
world has its own specific claim that human life as whole must have its own
end, although it is an end not in this life but in a future life.
Kant
gives the moral arguments instead of the theoretical arguments for the
immortality of the soul:
1. The highest good is a necessary object of
the will.
2. Holiness, or complete fitness of intentions
to the moral law, is necessary condition of the highest good.
3. Holiness cannot be found in a
sensuous rational being. It can be reached only in an endless progress and
since holiness is required, such endless progress toward it is the true object
of the will such progress can be endless only if the personality of the
rational being endures endlessly.
4. The highest good can be made real, only on
“the supposition of the immortality of the soul.
There arises a problem if we look
out for unknown happiness in the unknown world because, it would go against the
self rewarding morality proposed by Kant and it leads to the failure of
achieving happiness in the natural lives. So in the second critique Kant would
argue that we need immortality, not to achieve happiness not at all but rather
in order to make endless progress toward the complete conformity of dispositions
with the moral law, that is, toward virtue or worthiness to be happy.
Kant gives another proof for the existence of God. The
postulates of God and immortality compute the happiness in proposition to
worthiness to be happy ensuring that here is a power and a place for the
fulfillment of the proof for existence of God. Kant also makes it clear that
the postulate of immortality is that which cannot be known but can only be
thought. Kant also claims that his arguments for immortality do not provide us
with any theoretical laws but only practical and objective truth that can give
rise to actions based on motives, and, above all, sustain a moral agent in the
moral nature involved in making human worthy of highest good.
2.2.3 The Postulate of Freedom
Kant gives an important placer for freedom
in his postulates of morality. Freedom is considered as logically possible and
practically useful concept in the Critique of Pure Reason. The special
statues given to freedom can be being readout from the Critique of Practical
Reason: Freedom, however among all the ideas of speculative reason is the
only possibility we know a priori. We do not understand it, but we know it as
the condition of the moral law which we know. The ideas of God and immortality
are, on the contrary, not conditions of the moral law, but only conditions of
the necessary object of a will which is determined by this law, this will being
morally the practical use of our pure reason. He
also asserts that freedom is “the key stone of the whole architecture of the system
of pure reason and even speculative reason.”
Freedom in its positive conception
should not be given a theoretical employment. The role of idea of freedoms and
the intelligible world is, practical. It provides an idea of ourselves which
motives us to obey the moral law. It is impossible to give empirical or theoretical evidence for freedom. Kant
says that, “It is therefore moral law, of which we become immediately conscious
can soon as we draw up maxims of the will of ourselves that offers itself to us
and lead directly to the concept of freedom.” Kant also gives a theoretical proof
of the reality of our freedom he held the view that we could infer the reality
of our freedom from the consciousness by means of the principle that ought
implies can.
Kant’s thought on freedom of the
will can be asserted through five phases. It is as follows:
·
Kant
asserts that free human actions are those that have internal rather than
external causes.
·
We
cannot prove the existence of free human actions which are not dictated by
deterministic laws of nature.
·
It
is possible to prove the existence of human freedom and thereby also prove that
moral law applies to us.
·
We
can prove the freedom of our will form the indisputable fact of our religion.
·
The
existence of free will simply implies the in escapable possibility of human
evil but equally the concomitantly indestructible possibility of human
conversions to goodness.
According to Kant the ideas of God and immortality gain
objective reality and legitimacy and in subjective necessity freedom is given
fundamental importance. As Kant states in Critique of Practical Reason:
The concept of freedom, in so far as its reality is proved by an apodictic law
of practical reason, is the key stone of the whole architecture of the system
of pure reason and even of speculative reason. All other concepts (like God and
Immortality), which are mere ideas, are unsupported by anything in speculative
reason are now attached themselves to the concept of freedom and gain, with
stability and objective reality. That is, their possibility is proved by the
fact that really there is freedom, and this idea is revealed by moral law. Though
freedom is given a special status, it does not mean that it is totally
different from other postulates. As we are neither in a position to prove their
reality by speculative reason nor to refute them, pre supposing that all three
postulates are a need of pure practical reason, which is based on duty to make
the highest good the object of the will.
2.3
CONCEPT
OF FREEDOM
Freedom
is a pivotal condition of Kantian philosophy, including both its theoretical
and practical sections. One of the important quotes of Kant about freedom is
that “Freedom is independence of the
compulsory will of another, and in so far as it tends to exist with the freedom
of all according to a universal law, it is the one sole original inborn right
belonging to every man in virtue of his humanity”. Freedom
has two important qualities, which were first described by the early modern
conception of freedom developed by Machiavelli: freedom involves both
independence from any form of dependency – freedom from and the power
for a subject to legislate for itself – freedom to.
The
most important belief about noumena is that Kant thinks only practical
philosophy can justify concerns about human freedom. On Kant’s view Freedom is
important because moral judgment presupposes that we are free in the sense that
we have the ability to do otherwise. To understand this, Kant gives an example
of a man who commits a theft. Basing on this example, Kant holds that in order
for this man's action to be morally wrong, it must have been within his control
in the sense that it was within his power at the moment not to have committed
the theft. If this was not within his control at the moment, then, while it may
be useful to punish him in order to shape his behavior or to influence others,
it nevertheless would not be correct to say that his action was morally wrong. Moral rightness and wrongness apply only to free agents who control their
actions and have it in their power, at the time of their actions, either to act
rightly or not. According to Kant, this is just common sense.
Kant rejects
the compatibilism of Leibniz. On the compatibilist view, as Kant
understands it, I am free whenever the cause of my action is within me. So I am
not free only when something external to me pushes or moves me, but I am free
whenever the proximate cause of my body's movement is internal to me as an acting
being. The
reason is ultimately that the causes of these movements occur in time. As in
the case of theft example, the compatibilist would say that the thief's action
is free because its proximate cause is inside him, and because the theft was
not an involuntary convulsion but a voluntary action. The thief decided to
commit the theft, and his action flowed from this decision. According to Kant,
however, if the thief's decision is a natural phenomenon that occurs in time,
then it must be the effect of some cause that occurred in a previous time.
According to
Kantian thought, even if the cause of my action is internal to me, if it is in
the past — for example, if my action today is determined by a decision I made yesterday,
or from the character I developed in childhood — then it is not within my
control now. The matter is not whether the cause of my action is internal or
external to me, but whether it is in my control now. For Kant, however, the
cause of my action can be within my control only if it is not in time. Here
comes the importance of transcendental idealism, which is the only way to make
sense of the kind of freedom that morality requires. For transcendental
idealism allows that the cause of my action may be a thing in itself outside of
time: namely, my noumenal self, which is free because it is not part of nature.
No matter what kind of character I have developed or what external influences
act on me, on Kant's view all of my intentional, voluntary actions are
immediate effects of my noumenal self, which is causally undetermined. My
noumenal self is an uncaused cause outside of time, which therefore is not
subject to the deterministic laws of nature in accordance with which our
understanding constructs experience.
Kant calls upon
the transcendental idealism to make a sense of freedom. According to Kant, if
morality requires that I am transcendentally free, then it seems that my true
self, and not just an aspect of my self, must be outside of time. If only my
noumenal self is free, and freedom is required for moral responsibility, then
my phenomenal self is not morally responsible.
In Critique of Pure reason,
Kant introduces the concept of spontaneity as the theoretical analogue of
freedom; here he also refers to cosmological and practical sense of freedom. By
the former he understands the power of bringing a state spontaneously
and describes it as reason creating for itself the idea of a spontaneity which
can bring to act itself, without requiring to be determined to action by an
antecedent cause in accordance with law and causality. This spontaneity is thus
opposed to natural causes, and has the ground for its determination within
itself. This spontaneity is described as one of the source of knowledge along
with receptivity. He opposes the spontaneity of imagination and understanding to the receptivity
of the sensibility. Spontaneity is the power of producing representation from
itself; but it is a power incapable of producing knowledge without the contribution
of receptivity. For the spontaneous act of synthesis to take place there has to
be something present in sensibility to be synthesized.
In Groundwork of Metaphysics of Morals
freedom is defined negatively and positively. At first, “The will is a kind of
causality belonging to living beings in so far as they are rational; freedom
would be the possibility of this causality that makes it effective independent
of any determination by alien causes” in the second, freedom consists in the self legislation, “what else then, can
freedom of will be but autonomy, i.e. the property that the will has of being a
law unto itself?”
The imperative appropriate for such
a conception of freedom can be neither hypothetical nor material; but are
categorical and formal. They are “not concerned with the matter of action and
its intended result, but rather with the form of the action and the principle
from which it follows.”Yet these actions have to be effective in a world of space and time overwhelmed
by competing and incompatible material ends. If the imperative had no
application in this world then it would be empty like the pure spontaneity of
the understanding. The outcome was a bifocal moral philosophy: at its most
ambitious but ill-focused extreme, autonomy in the core of a metaphysically
grounded account of freedom. But at the other extreme it is but the modest
basis of a canonical principle for testing maxims of action.
2.4
CONCEPT
OF OBLIGATION
What
stands out in Kant’s morality through which we govern ourselves is that there
are some actions we simply have to do. We impose a moral law on ourselves, and
the law gives rise to obligation, to a necessity to act in a certain ways. For
Kant, morality is not something which rises from a virtuous disposition that
forces us to help others. He sees always it as a struggle.
As mentioned earlier, the
contemporary lawyers of Kant held the view that punishment is necessary in
order to make others obey the natural laws. This view was built into the
concept of obligation. They held that obligation could only be explained as
necessity imposed by a law backed by threats of punishment for disobedience. So they thought Kant’s view, that we can make and motive ourselves to obey the
moral law is mere foolishness. In opposition to this view, the British
philosophers Shaftsbury and Hutcheson described virtue rather than law and
obligation as central to morality. They argued that to be virtuous we have only
to act regularly and deliberately from benevolent motives that we naturally
approve. Because approval is naturally felt by everyone, and because we have
benevolent motives, we can all equally see and do what morality calls for,
without need of external guidance or of sanctions. Christian Wolff, a
contemporary of Kant, tried to reach a similar conclusion by a similar route.
Kant came to hold that neither of these
kinds of moral theory was acceptable. They imply that the only necessity
involved in morality is the necessity of using a means to end your desire. If
you do not want the end, there is no need for you to do the act that leads to
it. But Kant thinks that it is just a contingent empirical fact that you have
the desire you have. If so, then on these views it is a matter of coincidence
whether or not someone is bound by any moral necessity. Thus obligation becomes
a matter of what one wants to do.
2.5
CATEGORICAL
IMPERATIVES
The
Categorical Imperative is the central philosophical concept in the moral
philosophy of Immanuel Kant, introduced in Kant's Groundwork of Metaphysics
of Morals. It may be defined as a way of evaluating motivations for action.
It is very difficult to interpret this work, but it is filled with depth of
insight and has a quality to make impact on the reader. Kant says that the sole
aim of his book is to seek out and establish the supreme principle of
morality. While defining an imperative, Kant makes distinction between command and
imperative. “The conception of an objective principle, in so far as it is
necessitating for a will, is called a command and the formula of the command is
called an imperative.” According to Kant, human beings occupy a special place in creation, and
morality can be summed up in one ultimate commandment of reason, or imperative,
from which all duties and obligations derive. He defined an imperative as any
proposition that declares a certain action (or inaction) to be necessary.
There
are three kinds of imperatives, corresponding to three different kinds or sense
of good action. Only one of these imperative is said to be moral imperative.
The following sentence is an example for imperative, if you wish to learn French;
you ought to take these means. Here there are two things to notice; first, the
actions commanded are conceived as being good with a view to attaining an end.
They are not the actions which ought to be performed for their own sake, but
only as a means. The imperative is thus to be called hypothetical. Secondly, the end here is not one which everyone seeks by nature. A man may
wish or not wish to learn French. The imperative means that if you wish to
learn French, you ought to take certain means that is performing certain
actions. This type of imperative is called by Kant a problematic Hypothetical
imperative. This type of imperative is not a moral imperative. The actions
commanded are commanded simply as useful for the attainment of an end which one
may or may not desire to attain; and the pursuit may or may not be compatible
with moral law. Hypothetical imperatives are an action based on desire. It is a directive to
the effect that if you wish to achieve such and such an end, you must act in
such and such way. Thus they are concerned with prudential actions. It is also
a command of reason. An example is that; be honest so that people may think
good of you.
Kant
doesn’t consider Hypothetical imperative as moral imperative. He is somewhat
cavalier in his treatment of teleological ethical theories. He doesn’t seem to
give sufficient consideration to a distinction which has to be made between
different types of teleological ethics. Kant expressed extreme dissatisfaction
with the popular moral philosophy of his day, believing that it could never
surpass the level of hypothetical imperatives; which tell us the means we could
achieve our ends. They do not tell us about ends we should choose. If a
utilitarian says that murder is wrong because it does not maximize good for
those who involved, this is irrelevant to people who are concerned only with
maximizing the positive outcome for themselves. Consequently, Kant argued,
hypothetical moral systems cannot convince moral action or be regarded as bases
for moral judgments against others, because the imperatives on which they are
based rely too heavily on subjective considerations. Happiness
may be considers as a subjective state which is acquired by certain actions but
which is distinct from these actions. In this case the actions are judged good
simply as means to an end to which they are external. But ‘happiness’ if we
follow, for instance, the customary way of translating Aristotle’s eudaimonia,
may be regarded as an objective actualization of the potentialities of man as
man, and these actions are not purely external to the end. Kant presented a moral system, based on the demands of the categorical
imperative, as an alternative. Kant rejects all Hypothetical imperatives, from
moral imperatives. He says that moral imperatives must be Categorical. Categorical
imperative is purely a priori, by considering the mere concept of a
categorical imperative; it commands conformity to law in general.
A
categorical imperative denotes an absolute, unconditional requirement that
asserts its authority in all circumstances, both required and justified as an
end in itself. By identifying a good will as the only unconditional
good, he denies that the principle of good willing can be fixed by reference to
an objective good or telos at which they aim. Rather than assuming a
determinate account of the good, and using this as the basis for determining what
we ought to do, he uses an account of the principles of ethics to determine
what is to have a good will. He asks one question: what maxims or fundamental
principles could be adopted by a plurality of agents without assuming anything
specific about the agent’s desire or their social relations? He further adds
principles that cannot be served for a plurality of agents have to be rejected:
the thought is that nothing could be a moral principle which cannot be a
principle for all. Morality begins with the rejection of non-universalizable
principles. The idea is formulated as a demand, and calls it Categorical
Imperative.
2.5.1
The First Formulation
The
first formulation of Categorical Imperative which is also known as the
Formula of Universal Law’ stated as follows: "Act only according to
that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it should become a
universal law.” This is the important formulation in Kant’s ethics. The indication of first
formulation is this: an agent who adopts a maxim of promising falsely could not
will it as a universal law. If the person where to do so he would be
committed to the predictable result that that trust would break down so that he
could act on his initial maxim of promising falsely. The formulation states
that a maxim of false formulation is not universalizable hence cannot be
included among the shared of any plurality of beings. The maxim of rejecting of
false promising is morally required; the maxim of promising falsely morally
forbidden. It is important to note that, Kant doesn’t think false promising
wrong because of its presumed unpleasant effects but it cannot be willed as a
universal principle.
Kant distinguishes two modes of ethical
assessment. At first we might evaluate the maxims that agents adopt. By discerning
this we will be able to pick out those who reject non-universalizable
principles (so have morally worthy principles) and those who adopt
non-universalizable principles (so have morally unworthy principles). Kant
speaks of those who hold morally worthy principles as acting out of duty.
However, Kant holds that we do not have certain knowledge either of our own or
of others’ maxims. We normally infer agents’ maxim or underlying principles
from the pattern of their action, yet no pattern will pick out a unique maxim.
For example, the activity of a genuinely honest shop keeper may not differ from
that of the reluctantly honest shopkeeper, who deals fairly only out of desire
for a good business reputation and would cheat if a safe opportunity arouse. Hence
for ordinary purposes we can often do no more than concern ourselves with
outward conformity to maxims of duty, rather than with claims that an act was
done out of such a maxim. Kant also speaks of an action that would have to be done by anyone who has a morally
worthy maxim as actions in accordance with duty. Such action is
obligatory and its omission forbidden.
2.5.2
The Second Formulation
The
second formulation of Categorical Imperative which is also known as the
formula of end in itself, is: “act so as to treat man, in your own person as
well as in that of anyone else, always as an end, never merely as a means.” It demands that we treat humanity in our own person or in the person of any
other never simply as a means but always at the same time as an end. It is the
highly articulated version of a demand for respect for persons. Instead of
demanding that we check that all could adopt the same maxims, it demands less
directly that we act in ways that respect, so leave intact, others’ capacities
to act.
The
first indication of the formulation is that, at first, one who thinks about
suicide will ask himself whether his action is consistent with the idea of man
as an end in itself. If he destroys himself to escape oppressive
conditions, he uses a person merely as a means to maintain a tolerable
condition until life ends. But man is not a thing, something which is to be
used merely as means, but all his actions must always be considered as an end
in itself. So, I cannot dispose man in any way to man in my own person so as to
mutilate, damage or kill him.
The
second indication is that, regarding obligatory duty towards others, whoever is
thinking of making a lying promise to others will see at once that he would be
using another man merely as a means, without the latter being the end in
itself. The person whom I propose to use by such a promise of my own purposes cannot
possibly assent to my way of acting toward him/her. This conflict with the
principle of duty towards others becomes more obvious if we consider examples
of attacks on the liberty and property of others. Here it is clear that whoever
transgresses the rights of men/women intends to use the person of others merely
as means without considering that as rational beings they shall always be
regarded as end also; that is, as beings who could possibly be the end of very
same action.
Kant interprets of the moral failure of
not treating others as ends as an alternative basis for an account of
the virtues. To treat others who are specifically human in their finitude –
hence vulnerable and needy – as ends requires that we support one
another’s capacities to act, to adopt maxims and to pursue their particular
ends. Hence it requires at least some support for others’ project and purposes.
Kant holds that this requires at least a limited beneficence. Although he does
not establish an unrestricted obligation of beneficence, such as utilitarians
hold to, he does argue for an obligation to reject a policy of refusing needed
help. Failure to treat others or oneself as ends is once again seen as a
failure of virtue or imperfect obligation. Imperfect obligations cannot prescribe universal performance: we can neither
help all in need, nor develop all possible talents. We can however, refuse to
make indifferent of either sort basic of our lives – and may find that
rejecting principled indifference demands a lot. Even a commitment of this
nature, taken seriously, will demand much. If we honor it, we have on Kant’s
account shown respect for persons and specifically for human dignity.
2.5.3
The Third Formulation
The
third formulation of Categorical imperative which is also known as the Formula
of Autonomy is “Therefore every rational being must so act as if he were
through his maxim always a legislative member in the universal kingdom of ends.” The idea of rational beings as ends in themselves, which is united with that of
rational will or practical reason as morally legislating, bring us to the
concept of ends. Kant says that I understand by a kingdom the systematic union
of rational beings through common laws. And because these laws have in view the
relation of these beings to one another as ends and means, as Kant puts it, it
can be called a kingdom of ends. A rational being can belong to this kingdom in
either of two ways. He belongs to it as a member when he is subjected to given
laws. He belongs to it as a sovereign or supreme head when, while legislating
he is not subject to the will of any other. Every rational being is both member
and sovereign; for no rational being is, when legislating and as legislating,
subject to the will of another. It is possible to take supreme head as
referring to God. For Kant rational being can occupy the place of supreme head
only if he is a completely independent being without want and without
limitation.
CONCLUSION
Morality
is highly related with human being. As human being is the part of the society,
he/she is more inclined to moral values. Kant’s moral thought stress on the
importance of man as a rational being. His philosophy is highly influential in
considering the dignity of human person. It is the moral principles that create
the sense of human and social values in society. Moral principles help not only
to lead a harmonious life, but also to create a sense of freedom and justice in
the society. It is the moral principles which create in man a sense of human
dignity and a sense of rational free will. The second formulation of
categorical imperative is a best example for this in which it exhorts man
should not be considered as merely a means but as an end. As I finished the second chapter I understood
one thing that Kant gives predominant importance to human person’ especially in
the concepts of his autonomy, free will etc.
Kant’s morals or
practical philosophy is developed not merely as a theoretical philosophy, but
as a practical implication. Kantian philosophy, in a greater sense has
proclaimed the dignity of human beings; mainly through the concept of freedom,
autonomy, obligation and free will. This chapter was an enquiry into the
analysis of how the concept of human being is developed in Kantian thinking and
also to discover how he proved human as an ethical being through his moral
principles.
This
chapter was mainly dealing with Kantian concept of autonomy and concept of free
will which was helpful in showing the dignity of mankind. The discussion on his
‘postulates of morality’ such as God, immortality and freedom, analyzes the
basic character of humans, as ethical beings. Through God, he shows the end of
humans’ moral actions. The third part mainly discussed on the concept of
freedom in human beings. The fourth part was on his conception of obligation.
The fifth and last part of this chapter discussed his categorical
Imperatives where Kant establishes certain underlining principles on
morality.
CHAPTER
3
CRITICISM
OF KANT’S THINKING
INTRODUCTION
I found it difficult to look with a critical mind into the ethical
thought of such a great philosopher Immanuel Kant, because his ethical thought
is perhaps both the finest and the most characteristic product of the
Enlightenment period. We know that Kant’s thoughts have the background of
Rationalist and Empirical ways of thinking. He aimed to resolve disputes between empirical and rationalistic approaches. The
former asserted that all knowledge comes through experience; the latter
maintained that reason and innate ideas were prior. But Kant argued that
experience is purely subjective without first being processed by pure reason.
He added that, using reason without applying it to experience, only leads to
theoretical illusions. Thus a philosophy of unifying the two divergent thinking
in modern era was a commendable step of Kant and it was a new epoch in the
modern thinking. The free and proper exercise of reason by the individual was a
theme of Kant's approaches to the various problems of philosophy. An attempt to
criticize it is both a theoretical exercise and a part of an ongoing praxis
that aims at supporting, opposing or transforming the movement itself.
While looking into the ethical
thoughts of Kant, we come to know that his thoughts are marked by an unswerving
commitment to human freedom, the dignity of man and to the view that moral
obligation derives neither from God, nor from human authorities and
communities, nor from the preferences or desires of human agents, but from
reason. I think, while analyzing Kant’s ethics we have to look deep into his early
parts of writings. Secondly, the developments added in his ethics by the
thinkers after the Kantian era. Finally, we have to keep in mind that Kant’s
ethics is used as an admiring label even today in the contemporary ethical
positions.
A philosophical position is said to
be relevant if and only if it has still influence in the changing patterns of
the society. It is sure that every thinking pattern has a positive and negative
impact in the society. Thus while criticizing Kant’s ethics; I thought to
analyze his ethics in relation with the contemporary thinking patterns. For
that purpose, this chapter is divided into three parts; the first part deals
with the criticism of Kant’s ethics in general in relation to the contemporary
society, in the second part I tried to analyze his postulates of morality and
the third part is the analysis of his Categorical Imperatives.
3.1 CRITICISM OF
KANT’S ETHICS IN
GENERAL
The general criticisms on Kant’s ethics are
scientifically explained by experts in certain terms. Such general criticisms
are discussed in the following lines.
3.1.1 Rigorism
This
is the claim that Kant’s ethics leads to rigidly insensitive rules, and so cannot
take account of differences between cases. However, universal principles need
not command uniform treatment; indeed they may command differentiated
treatment. Principles such as taxation should be proportionate to ability to
pay or the punishment must fit the crime are universal statements but demand
differentiated treatment. Even principles that do not specifically command
differentiated treatment will be indeterminate.
3.1.2 Abstraction
Those
who admit that Kant’s arguments identify some principles of duty, but do not
impose rigid uniformity, often move on with the claim of the criticism of
formalism. They will say that Kant identifies ethical principles, but these
principles are too abstract to guide action, because his theory is not action –
guiding. Kant’s principles of duty are abstract, and he does not provide a detailed set
of instructions for following them.
3.1.3 Conflicting grounds of Obligation
This
criticism points out that Kantian ethics identifies a set of principles which
may come into conflict. This criticism is true of Kant’s ethics. Since trade-offs between differing obligations
are not part of the theory, there is no routine procedure for dealing with
conflicts. On the other hand, since the theory is only a set of slide constrain
on action, the central demand is to find some actions that falls within all
constrains. Only when no such actions can be found, the problem of multiple
grounds of obligation made by advocates of virtue ethics has unavoidably to be
violated or neglected, as appropriate.
3.1.4 Place of Inclinations
A
group of serious criticism of Kant’s moral psychology occurs throughout the
secondary literature. In particular it is said that Kant’s requires that we act
out of the motive of duty, hence not
out of inclinations, and so is driven to the claim that action which we enjoy
cannot be morally worthy. This grim interpretation, perhaps first suggested by
Schiller, involves a tangle of difficult issues. By acting out of the motive of
duty, Kant means only we act on a maxim of duty and so experience a feeling of reverence for the law. This reverence is
a response to and not the source of moral worth. It is compatible with action
being in line with our natural inclinations and so enjoyed. On the view the
clear conflict between duty and inclination is only epistemological; we can
know that we act out of duty only if inclinations is lacking. On other views, the issue run deeper, and leads to a more serious charge that
Kant cannot account for wrongdoing.
3.1.5 No Account of Wrongdoing
This
criticism is that Kant can allow only for free action which is fully autonomous
– i.e. done on a principle that meets the limit that all others can do likewise
– and for action which reflects only natural desires and inclinations. Hence we
cannot allow for free, imputable but wrong action. Clearly Kant thinks that he
can give an account of wrongdoing, for he frequently gives examples of
imputable wrongdoing. This criticism probably reflects a failure to keep
separate the claim that free agents must be capable of acting autonomously with
the claim that free agents always act autonomously. Imputability requires the
capacity to act autonomously but this capacity may not always be exercised.
Wrongful acts are indeed not autonomous, but they are chosen rather than
inflicted mechanically by our desires or inclinations.
3.2 CRITICISM OF KANT’S POSTULATES OF MORALITY
Kant’s
structure has strong foundation in rationality, but this rationality alone
could not be used to give fullness and perfection to his theory. He
incorporated the postulates of God, Immortality and freedom as an attempt to
limit the theoretical and to extend the practical usefulness. While analyzing
the postulates we become skeptical of Kant’s philosophical structure built on
rationality and it evokes a question in our mind whether it is a last minute
attempt by Kant to save his thinking structure. Regarding the mentioning of
postulates, Kant has received criticism from many sides. One such Criticism is
by Neiman, following Hegel he holds that, “Kant’s postulates of reason are
pitiful substitutes for the truth that it failed to establish.” Another criticism arising from incorporating postulates is that, postulates
become meaningful only to a person who is moral and for a person who turns a
blind eye towards it becomes impossible to objectively identify the reality of
God, freedom and immortality. “If there were to be someone who was genuinely
deaf to the call of moral obligation or totally indifferent to the question
whether the world could be made better or not, he could not even understand
what the proof was about.” That is, if the postulates are taken of their practical context then they may
not become that much useful. Kant’s denial of theoretical knowledge to bring in
the practical postulates does not satisfactorily formulate the intrinsic
connection which Kant is trying to establish between morality and metaphysics.
The postulates, brought in to the critical philosophy not because of their
metaphysical existence and epistemological knowledge but by their
transcendental (practical) reality are crucial for human life as it give a
moral certitude by which we can respond to the demands of moral law.
Kantian notion of the Postulate
of God is said to have a pragmatic approach. As mentioned in the second chapter
Kant already has given the reason for a necessary God. “To be happy is necessarily the
desire of every rational finite being, and thus it is an unavoidable finite
being, and thus it is an unavoidable determinant of its faculty of desire.” Kant introduces God as a reward giver for the moral worthiness of human beings.
For him God is the only one who sees the intention behind the deeds of the
individual. The individual may not always get the correct remark from the
community for one’s deeds and often may get blamed for one’s action, without
looking into the intension of one’s act. So he introduced God to solve this
problem, and to initiate man to live a trustworthy life.
This notion seems rational, but it
has some problem. Kant introduced God as a reward giver for the moral
worthiness of the individual. The first problem is that, if Kant’s thought is
accepted, God will be placed just as reward giver for the actions of human
being which will result in pragmatism. Secondly, God is placed as reward giver
for the moral actions of individual, and if there is no human being there won’t
be moral acts. Thus according to Kant’s thought if there are no human beings
then the existence of God is questioned.
3.3 CRITICISM OF KANT’S CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVES
In
his book Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, philosopher Immanuel
Kant gives a concise definition of his basis for morals, which he calls the categorical imperative. Kant states
“There is, therefore, only a single categorical imperative and it is this: “act
only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time will
that it become a universal law.” This is the foundational element of his entire system of morals.
The
common blame against Kant’s ethics is the claim that the Categorical Imperative
is empty, trivial or purely formal and identifies no principles of duty. This
criticism holds mainly by Hegel and J.S. Mill in their works. On Kant’s view,
the demand for universalizable maxims is a demand that our fundamental principles
are fit for adoption by all. This condition can seem pointless: because no well
formed act description can be prescribed by a universal principle. Common
principles like steal when you can or
kill when it isn’t risky cannot be
made universalizable. This reductio ad absurdum of universalizability is
achieved by replacing Kant’s Categorical imperative with a different principle. Kant gives certain examples to say about the application of the categorical
imperative. For example a man who sees someone in need but declines to offer
help. According to Kant such a situation would not be moral. The reasons he
gives are not on the grounds of a wrong committed against the other person, but
because the action cannot be applied universally. Kant’s position is that we
all are persons who need help, and if the maxim is applied categorically, we
would all be denied the help we needed. If this law is applied universally, if anyone in the society were to desire
help, including ourselves, it would be a categorical imperative that we do not
render help to anyone. Such a maxim of ignoring those who are suffering is
perfectly rational and meets the categorical imperative, and if the categorical
imperative is applied consistently, it is reasonable violates no reason or
logic. But it violates the universal moral law engrained on human hearts, which
everyone including Kant finds it morally reprehensible.
Kant’s
application of the categorical imperative here is inconsistent, in fact only
due to his inability to view situations apart from his concept of Christian
perspective. The system of Kant worked
for a long time because he lived in a time where Christian doctrines where so
influencing. But if it is applied to a society of complete absence from a
theistic moral perspective, Kant’s categorical imperative becomes quite
immoral. The formula of universal law demands not just that we formulate a universal
principle incorporating some act- description that applies to a given act. It
demands that an agent’s maxim, or fundamental principle, be such that the agent
can will it as universal law. The
test requires dedication to be normal, predictable consequences of principles
to which the agent is committed and to normal standards of instrumental
rationality. When maxims are non – universalizable, commitment to the consequences of their
universal adoption would be incompatible with commitment to the means of acting
on them.
Kant’s
account of universalizability has two problems. First, it does not refer to
what universally done. Second, it is a procedure only for picking out the
maxims that must be rejected if the fundamental principles of a life or a
society are to be universalizable. Non – universalizable principles are
identified in order to discover the side constraints on the more specific
principles agents may adopt. These side constraints enable us to identify more specific but still
indeterminate principles of obligation. The following is a detailed description
about the above said facts on Categorical Imperatives.
The
first categorical imperative states that: "Act only according to that
maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it should become a universal
law.” Kant introduces this imperative in his ethics in order to establish a water
tight law in making people to act well and good in the society. An imperative
where giving permission to act upon one’s own will under the condition that,
his action should be able to perform universally, is acceptable because it
makes the person to think whether each
of his/her action is universally acceptable or not. But at the same time while
looking deep into it, there seem some problems for this imperative. These
problems are fourfold:
The
first, problem can be explained with an example, if a jar contains only purple
and red jelly beans, then if you remove all the red jelly beans then there
remain only purple jelly beans. It seems wrong to think that; an imperative can
contain universality and an end, in the same way a jar can contain two flavors
of jelly beans. If it is related with the concept of form
and matter of the imperative, then
their relation seems quite different: because, they cannot exist independently.
There is no such thing as form without matter or matter without form. If we
'remove' the matter of a proposition, that is exactly like removing the
proposition as such and there remains nothing left. The notion of a proposition
that has nothing to it except a universal form, without any particular content,
seems to be meaningless.
The
second problem is that, the reason behind obeying the categorical imperative is
supposed to be a good thing is that, to do so constitutes conforming one's
actions to law as such or the universality of law as such. That
there is no such thing as conformity to law
as such should be evident. The problem is that as Kant says, we cannot
confirm the universality of the law
as such but we can confirm only to a
particular law. For example, doing harm to others is wrong. But in certain circumstances it can
be used as a self protection of the life of the individual.
The
third problem is that, the first categorical imperative doesn't really tell us
what actions to be performed. Instead, it tells us what sort of maxims to act
on, or in other words, under what maxims to perform the actions. The
categorical imperative represents a test on maxims or rules of conduct; that
is, a necessary condition of their acceptability. This would be all right, if
only the condition were strict enough to determine a unique set of acceptable
rules, or, excluding that, at least a greatly limited number.
While
analyzing the first categorical imperative we come to know the fact that
categorical imperatives says very little about morality. The first categorical
imperative rules out actions whose maxims include (by definition) the fact that
other people are not doing the same thing. For example, if a person tries to
write some books by way of trying to become the best philosopher in the world,
or if the same person tries to be the best at anything, his/her maxim would not
be universalizable. An individual could not choose that everybody be the best. By the way, this is of course a counter-example to the Kantian principle. There
is nothing wrong with trying to be the best. There is nothing wrong as such with
doing things that, if someone does them, other person cannot.
The
second Categorical imperative is that, “act so as to treat man, in your own
person as well as in that of anyone else, always as an end, never merely as a
means.” Its first problem is ambiguity. That is because I know how to treat a state of
affairs as an end (namely, try to bring it about), but I don't know how to
treat an entity as an end. There arise a question, does treating a person as an end mean treating his existence
as an end? Should we, then, simply try to maximize the number of rational
beings existing? Kant does not say anything that sounds like this, but in his
second discussion of the honored duties towards others, he implies that
treating people as ends means treating their happiness as an end. This is why
we have a duty of helping people to achieve what they want. But there seems a
contradiction in his claim and rest of Kant's theory seems unclear, since he
previously insisted upon the utter worthlessness of all objects of inclination.
If
moral virtue is infinitely better than happiness and pleasure, then, just as we
must always sacrifice our own pleasure to moral virtue, must we not also
sacrifice others' happiness for the sake of moral virtue? Wouldn't the proper
thing be to treat people's moral virtue as an end, rather than either their
happiness or their existence? Thus we should have to go about preaching constantly to each other. This need
not involve harm to their happiness, but with the Kantian doctrine of the
incommensurability of values, it is unlikely anybody's happiness would ever
influence our actions. Although it's a theoretical possibility that two actions
could result in the same amount of moral virtue in the world but one produce
more happiness, so that the latter should be chosen, it is infinitely unlikely
this would ever happen. That two quantities should be exactly equal, or that an
action influencing our happiness should have no effect whatsoever on our moral
virtue, is an extremely small possibility. We therefore can for all practical purposes disregard about any concerns of
benefitting others or ourselves, and focus all our energies on trying to get
people to obey the categorical imperative.
While
analyzing the Categorical Imperative there arise a question why should we treat
people as end and never merely as means? The answer we get will be that, it is
because human being possesses intrinsic, incommensurable value. Then why do
human beings possess such value? The answer will be they are capable to act
morally and dutiful action is the incomparable good in the world. According to
Kant, there are duties, but he didn’t think that action according to false
moral principles as good. Moral action is good only if we act according to our
obligation. And when we go deep into the concept of duty, we come to know that
the duty there is to treat the humanity as ends. The absolute worth human being
can be warranted if only if Kant can show his argument as obligation. I think
while analyzing the concept of obligation in Kant he tried to point out that,
if there is an obligation, it is an obligation to do an act rather than seeing
whether the other person does it.
The
second Categorical Imperative can be analyzed with certain exemplar situations.
If taking the situation of committing suicide, according to Kant’s thinking a
person commits suicide because, the person sees himself /herself as a means
instead of an end. It is a case of treating one’s existence as a means for
one’s happiness. If happiness of humanity is the end, then any one can commit
suicide, because people commit suicide to get away from pain. This is said to
be a great fault that Kant made in the concept of treating humanity as an end.
Taking
the case of breaking the promise, it constitutes treating other person as
means, namely the person to whom the promise was made. The problem here is that
according to Kant’s concept it failed to treat the other person’s happiness as
an end in itself. Because breaking the promise probably turns the promise unhappy.
Thus according to Kant this action becomes immoral.
The
practical implication of second Categorical Imperative seems to turn negative
impacts in the society. While analyzing the meaning of treating humanity as an end, it seems to be treating the perfection
of humanity as an end in itself. Since this may interfere with taking our
happiness as an end in itself, we should be equally entitled to say that the
person who develops his talents is failing to regard himself (his happiness) as
an end, as to say the person who neglects his talents fails to regard himself
as an end.
Another
problem regarding this is that, Kant reverts to the idea of treating humanity's
happiness as an end when he discusses the duty to help others. But once again
Kant's principle turns against him. He uses it to show that egoism, and
refusing to help others, is wrong, but can't it just as well be used to argue
that altruism is wrong? For, isn't the altruist just using himself as a means
for the sake of others' happiness? For example, if taking money from other people to use on yourself is treating
them merely as means and not as ends (and presumably taking their money for any
purpose, even to help some third party, would also be treating them as means)
then surely taking your own money and using it on others, by analogy, is
treating yourself as a means. Since the reason given for the second Categorical
Imperative is the absolute and incomparable
value of human beings, there is no way
to make choices between people. Since one cannot compare the value
of one person to that of another person, or to anything else, in a situation in
which one is given a choice between different people (suppose there are a
limited number of life jackets in a sinking boat), there is nothing one can do. If values are incommensurable, we cannot say a hundred deaths are worse than
one.
In
many cases this theory seems irrational. It ignores the fact that there are
situations in which we are forced to compare values. For example, the ruling
government has to decide, how much money to spend on health care if they take
health as an important value, and then there is no doubt on how much it can
consume from the entirety of the gross national product of the country, and
leave no time or resources for anything else. This is what absolute value in this sense will do. So it is logically impossible
to have multiple absolute and superseding values, they may come into conflict,
in which they cannot both be treated as absolute. Moreover, the concept of
incomparable values ends in mathematical absurdity. That is the notion of a
quantity that is neither greater nor less than, nor yet equal to, is a
mathematical absurdity.
CONCLUSION
Kant’s
ethical thought is one of the few products of the history of philosophy that
exercise such a strong continuing influence on us that replacing commonly
accepted ideas about it with more accurate and less oversimplified ones might
help to transform our conception of our own history and of ourselves as heirs
of the enlightenment. In this chapter I made an attempt to evaluate Kantian
ethical principles in the light of contemporary ethical situations.
Kantian conceptions of autonomy,
free will, obligation, categorical imperatives and postulates of morality seem
to be effective in the contemporary society too. The concept of autonomy shows
the fact that, as rational beings, human beings are capable of legislating
moral laws by their own, without any pressure from outside. Human being is the
part of certain kinds of external inclinations, but the effective understanding
of autonomy enables humans to become free.
We have to conclude that, no
philosophy, or moral thoughts were capable of giving a final solution for the
problems of the society. New moral consciousnesses develop when one supersedes
the other. Thus when we analyze Kant’s moral philosophy, though it cannot give
a complete answer to the problems of mankind, in many ways, in the present
society, in the realms of considering the dignity of human beings and promoting
individual freedom Kantian moral principles are applicable.
GENERAL CONCLUSION
“Change is the ultimate principle of universe”,
said by Heraclitus. He affirmed it by saying, “One man cannot step twice into
the same river. As they step into the same rivers, other and still other waters
flow upon them.” While considering moral principles which humans uphold, I think the above
statement is true. The society which man lives is changing. When we say about
the changes in the society, actually we are speaking about the changes in its
culture. In a deep study on the cultural change, we come to know that what
actually changes is the moral nature of the society. This change in the moral
consciousness is that what reflects in the lifestyle of individual’s life
patterns such as; family, religion, relationships, fashions etc.
While comparing the
past years, the contemporary society which we live today has undergone many
changes. If we take the example of women in the Indian society, the very
ancient society considered women as goddess and as light of the house
and gave her great honor. But in the medieval era, she is treated like a slave,
who must be obedient to men. The best example for this was the practice of Sati
and the Devadasi system. Today, the society began to think about the
dignity of women, and has started the slogan of women empowerment. But
one thing to be remembered is that, in either of these cases, the moral consciousnesses
imprinted in the humanity were not changed. What actually happened was that,
the compression or imprisonment of genuine morality by a mightier society. Yet,
there heard in the human heart the sigh for an evoking right morality.
Today, we are living
in a consumerist society, where the value of everything is determined by the
availability of the profit. Thus relationships, education, medical services
etc. has lost its original purity. In such a society, I think there starts the
relevance for such a strong ethical principle of Immanuel Kant. Kantian ethics
is grounded on the dignity of rational nature. While deciding to take Kantian
philosophy to analyze moral nature of human being, what was actually in my mind
was, his ethical thought is much useful in the present changing society.
Especially, I was attracted by his categorical imperatives, which proclaims for
a universal acceptable maxim and the concept of accepting humanity as an end in
themselves. In this dissertation my attempt was to find out whether, Kantian
moral principle is an answer for the contemporary social problems.
Kantian
philosophy was an intellectual movement of the enlightenment period. It was an
answer for the many then existing evils in the society. The enlightenment still
exists today, since many people throughout the world still struggle for the
expansion of liberty in human thought and action, equality in social, political
and economic spheres and tolerance regarding religious and cultural diversity.
I think Kantian morality is capable of upholding the dignity and freedom of
individuals even in the present society.
The
concept of autonomy is the core of his moral theory. He is in the
position that rational human wills are autonomous, which involves two
components; the first is that, no authority external to ourselves
is needed to constitute or inform us of the demands of morality. Each of us can
know without being told what we ought to do, because moral requirements are
requirements we impose on ourselves. The second is that in self-government we
can effectively control ourselves. The obligations we impose upon ourselves
supersede all other calls for action, and often run counter to our desires.
Thus his conception of autonomy itself tries to uphold the individual
dignity.
One of the important features of
Kant’s ethics is that, the change that he made from objective morality to that
of subjective morality. His conception of categorical imperatives is an example
for this. In a positive sense is highly useful in upholding the individual
dignity. The notion of self legislature of the law insists upon the
autonomy and supremacy of mankind. His first proclamation, in a positive sense
is useful if all people can uphold it. But it becomes useless in the negative
sense, because an individual may not be able to uphold a particular principle
in an ideal manner. The second categorical imperative is much useful in the
present society. When Kant says to treat human as an end, he meaning he gives
for end is happiness. Here Kant induces us to think about the Platonic
concept of Happiness. One of the problems regarding this imperative is that if
people do not understand the exact meaning of what Kant suggested, there is a
chance for others to act immorally.
Kant
introduced the three postulates into his morality taking into consideration the
fact that man is a creature haunted by inclinations. The postulates give
strength to his ethics. For
Kant, the concept of God arises because the relationship between moral law and
happiness is not guaranteed in this world. Here God comes to rescue and thus
necessitates the compatibility of virtue and realization of highest good. Kant
introduces God as reward giver for the moral act of human being. He places God
as a reward giver in order to induce human to act morally, but as mentioned
earlier there is a tendency to regard Kant’s concept of God as mere pragmatism.
The postulate of immortality is interwoven in the postulate of God. It is very
difficult for man to be righteous without hope. Immortality guarantees a
reckoning place of happiness. It is in the place of freedom that the self
legislation and autonomous nature of human being has its relevance. Freedom is
placed by Kant as an a priori notion for the condition moral law. It is because
of the freedom that the God and immortality gets legitimacy and subjective
necessity.
Kant played a central role in maintaining the value
of rational nature as an end in itself. Undergoing
both natural competitiveness and social antagonism, the human species, according
to Kant, develops the rational capacity to struggle against its impulses toward
a human community in which the ends of all are to harmonize and to coincide.
Thus we have to conclude that, Kant’s ethical vision is grounded in the idea of
the dignity of the rational nature of every human being.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
AMERIKS, Karl, Kant and the Fate of Autonomy (Cambridge, U.K: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
BEARDSLEY, M. C (ed.), The European
Philosophers from Descartes to Nietzsche (New
York, NY: The Modern Library, 1992).
BECK, Lews W., A Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason
(Chicago: The University of
Chicago Press, 1960).
CAYGILL, Howard, “Autonomy,” A Kant Dictionary (Oxford, U.K: Blackwell Publishers, 2000) 88-89.
CHACKALACKAL, Saju, Unity of Knowing and Acting in Kant: A
Paradigmatic Integration of Theoretical and Practical (Bangalore:
Dharmaram Publications, 2002).
COPLESTON, Frederic, A History of Philosophy (New York, NY:
Image Books, 1985) VI.
GARDNER, Sebastian, Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Kant and the Critique
of Pure Reason (New York,
NY: Routledge, 2002).
GRANGER, Herbert, “Kant, Immanuel,” Thomson Gale Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
Vol. 4, 316-321.
GRAYLING, A. C., Philosophy 1-A Guide through the Subject
(Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1998).
GUYER, Paul, Kant on Freedom, Law and Happiness (Cambridge U.K:
Cambridge University Press,
2000).
_____, Kant,
(New York, NY: Routledge Publishers, 2006).
_____, Philosophy 2 – Further Through
the Subject (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1998).
_____, The
Cambridge Companion to Kant (Cambridge, U.K: Cambridge University Press, 1992).
_____, “Kant, Immanuel,” Routledge
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. 5, 177-200.
____, “Kant, Immanuel,”
in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (ed. E. CRAIG) (London Routledge) Retrieved November
27, 2012, from http://www.rep... ………routledge.com/article/DB047SECT10.
JOHN, S. D., “German Writers in the Age of Goethe: Sturmund Drang to Classicissm,”
Dictionary of Literary Biography, Vol.9, 106-121.
KANT, Immanuel, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (ed. GREGOR
M.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1998).
KORSGAARD, Christine M., Morality as Freedom: Kant’s Practical
Philosophy Reconsidered, (Netherland: Klower Academic Publishers, 1986).
LEWIS, Clarens I “Kant, Immanuel,” Collier’s Encyclopedia, Vol. 13,
741-744.
O’NEILL, Onora, A Companion to Ethics
(ed. P. SINGER) (New York, NY: Blackwell Publishers, 1993).
SCHROEDER, William. R., Continental Philosophy: A Critical Approach
(Oxford, U.K: Blackwell Publishers,
2005).
STRAVSON, Gallon, “Free Will,” Routledge Encyclopedia of
Philosophy III, 743-752.
WALSH, W H, “Kant, Immanuel”, Thomson Gale Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. 5, 9-33.
WOOD, Allen W, Kant’s Ethical Thought (Cambridge, U.K: Cambridge
University Press, 1999).
“Kant, Immanuel”, Encyclopedia
Britannica, Vol. 10, 392.
“Postulate” in Oxford Advanced
Learners Dictionary, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006) 306.
“Autonomy” [online: linked from “Standford
Encyclopedia” home page, http://plato.standford.edu/entries/kant-moral/toc, Accessed September. 15, 2012].
“Free Will” [online: linked from “A
Quote by Immanuel Kant on Free Will,” home page,
http://blog.gaiam.com/quotes/authors/immanuel
Kant/53530, Accessed
September. 12, 2012].
“Freedom of Kant” [online: linked from
“Standford Encyclopedia” home page, http://plato.standford.edu/entries/kant-moral/toc, Accessed September. 15, 2012].
“The Critique of Judgment,” [online:
linked from “Wikipedia free encyclopedia” home
page,http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/ImmanuelKant. Accessed August. 5, 2012].
Comments
Post a Comment